Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

This page is about topology as a field of mathematics. For topology as a structure on a set, see topological space.

Parts of this page exists also in a German language version, see at Topologie.

I believe that we lack another analysis properly geometric or linear which expresses location directly as algebra expresses magnitude.

G. W. Leibniz (letter to Huygens 1679, according to Bredon 93, p. 430)

Idea

Topology is one of the basic fields of mathematics. The term is also used for a particular structure in a topological space; see topological structure for that.

The subject of topology deals with the expressions of continuity and boundary, and studying the geometric properties of (originally: metric) spaces and relations of subspaces, which do not change under continuous deformations, regardless to other (such as in their metric properties).

Topology as a structure enables one to model continuity and convergence locally. More recently, in metric spaces, topologists and geometric group theorists started looking at asymptotic properties at large, which are in some sense dual to the standard topological structure and are usually referred to as coarse topology.

There are many cousins of the concept of topological spaces, e.g. sites, locales, topoi, higher topoi, uniformity spaces and so on, which specialize or generalize some aspect or structure usually found in Top.

One of the tools of topology, homotopy theory, has long since crossed the boundaries of topology and applies to many other areas, thanks to many examples and motivations as well as of abstract categorical frameworks for homotopy like Quillen model categories, Brown’s categories of fibrant objects and so on.

Introduction

The following gives a quick introduction to some of the core concepts and tools of topology:

A detailed introduction is going to be at Introduction to Topology.

Continuity

The key idea of topology is to study spaces with “continuous maps” between them. The concept of continuity was made precise first in analysis, in terms of epsilontic analysis of open balls, recalled as def. below. Then it was realized that this has a more elegant formulation in terms of the more general concept of open sets, this is prop. below. Adopting the latter as the definition leads to the concept of topological spaces, def. below.

First recall the basic concepts from analysis:

(metric space)

A metric space is

such that for all x,y,z∈Xx,y,z \in X:

  1. d(x,y)=0⇔x=yd(x,y) = 0 \;\;\Leftrightarrow\;\; x = y

  2. (symmetry) d(x,y)=d(y,x)d(x,y) = d(y,x)

  3. (triangle inequality) d(x,y)+d(y,z)≥d(x,z)d(x,y)+ d(y,z) \geq d(x,z).

Every normed vector space (V,|−|)(V, {\vert - \vert}) becomes a metric space according to def. by setting

d(x,y)≔|x−y|. d(x,y) \coloneqq {\vert x-y \vert} \,.

(epsilontic definition of continuity)

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

For (X,d X)(X,d_X) and (Y,d Y)(Y,d_Y) two metric spaces (def. ), then a function

f:X⟶Y f \;\colon\; X \longrightarrow Y

is said to be continuous at a point x∈Xx \in X if for every ϵ>0\epsilon \gt 0 there exists δ>0\delta\gt 0 such that

d X(x,y)<δ⇒d Y(f(x),f(y))<ϵ d_X(x,y) \lt \delta \;\;\Rightarrow\;\; d_Y(f(x), f(y)) \lt \epsilon

or equivalently such that

f(B x ∘(δ))⊂B f(x) ∘(ϵ) f(\;B_x^\circ(\delta)\;) \;\subset\; B^\circ_{f(x)}(\epsilon)

where B ∘B^\circ denotes the open ball (definition ).

The function ff is called just continuous if it is continuous at every point x∈Xx \in X.

We now reformulate this analytic concept in terms of the simple but important concept of open sets:

(open ball)

Let (X,d)(X,d), be a metric space. Then for every element x∈Xx \in X and every ϵ∈ℝ +\epsilon \in \mathbb{R}_+ a positive real number, write

B x ∘(ϵ)≔{y∈X|d(x,y)<ϵ} B^\circ_x(\epsilon) \;\coloneqq\; \left\{ y \in X \;\vert\; d(x,y) \lt \epsilon \right\}

for the open ball of radius ϵ\epsilon around xx.

The following picture shows a point xx, some open balls B iB_i containing it, and two of its neighbourhoods U iU_i:

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

graphics grabbed from Munkres 75

(rephrasing continuity in terms of open sets)

A function f:X→Yf \colon X \to Y between metric spaces (def. ) is continuous in the epsilontic sense of def. precisely if it has the property that its pre-images of open subsets of YY (in the sense of def. ) are open subsets of XX.

First assume that ff is continuous in the epsilontic sense. Then for O Y⊂YO_Y \subset Y any open subset and x∈f −1(O Y)x \in f^{-1}(O_Y) any point in the pre-image, we need to show that there exists a neighbourhood of xx in f −1(O Y)f^{-1}(O_Y). But by assumption there exists an open ball B x ∘(ϵ)B_x^\circ(\epsilon) with f(B x ∘(ϵ))⊂O Yf(B_x^\circ(\epsilon)) \subset O_Y. Since this is true for all xx, by definition this means that f −1(O Y)f^{-1}(O_Y) is open in XX.

Conversely, assume that f −1f^{-1} takes open subsets to open subsets. Then for every x∈Xx \in X and B f(x) ∘(ϵ)B_{f(x)}^\circ(\epsilon) an open ball around its image, we need to produce an open ball B x ∘(δ)B_x^\circ(\delta) in its pre-image. But by assumption f −1(B f(x) ∘(ϵ))f^{-1}(B_{f(x)}^\circ(\epsilon)) contains a neighbourhood of xx which by definition means that it contains such an open ball around xx.

Topological spaces

Therefore we should pay attention to open subsets. It turns out that the following closure property is what characterizes the concept:

(closure properties of open sets in a metric space)

The collection of open subsets of a metric space (X,d)(X,d) as in def. has the following properties:

In particular

  • the empty set is open (being the union of no subsets)

and

  • the whole set XX itself is open (being the intersection of no subsets).

This motivates the following generalized definition:

The following shows all the topologies on the 3-element set (up to permutation of elements)

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

graphics grabbed from Munkres 75

It is now immediate to formally implement the

(continuous maps)

A continuous function between topological spaces

f:(X,τ X)→(Y,τ Y) f \colon (X, \tau_X) \to (Y, \tau_Y)

is a function between the underlying sets,

f:X⟶Y f \colon X \longrightarrow Y

such that pre-images under ff of open subsets of YY are open subsets of XX.

The simple definition of open subsets and the simple principle of continuity gives topology its fundamental and universal flavor. The combinatorial nature of these definitions makes topology closely related to formal logic (for more on this see at locale).

Our motivating example now reads:

One point of the general definition of “topological space” is that it admits constructions which intuitively should exist on “continuous spaces”, but which do not in general exist, for instance, as metric spaces:

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

The above picture shows on the left the square (a topological subspace of the plane), then in the middle the resulting quotient topological space obtained by identifying two opposite sides (the cylinder), and on the right the further quotient obtained by identifying the remaining sides (the torus).

graphics grabbed from Munkres 75

(product topological space)

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

For XX and YY two topological spaces, then the product topological space X×YX \times Y has

and

  • its open sets are those subsets O⊂X×YO \subset X \times Y of the Cartesian product such that for all point (x,y)∈O(x,y) \in O there exists open sets x∈O x⊂Xx \in O_x \subset X and y∈O Y⊂Yy \in O_Y \subset Y such that O x×O y⊂OO_x \times O_y \subset O.

graphics grabbed from Munkres 75

These constructions of discrete topological spaces, quotient topological spaces, topological subspaces and of product topological spaces are simple examples of limits and of colimits of topological spaces. The category Top of topological spaces has the convenient property that all limits and colimits (over small diagrams) exist in it. (For more on this see at Top – Universal constructions.)

Homeomorphism

With the objects (topological spaces) and the morphisms (continuous maps) of the category Top of topology thus defined, we obtain the concept of “sameness” in topology.

To make this precise, one says that a morphism

X→fY X \overset{f}{\to} Y

in a category is an isomorphism if there exists a morphism going the other way around

X⟵f −1Y X \overset{f^{-1}}{\longleftarrow} Y

which is an inverse in the sense that

f∘f −1=id Yandf −1∘f=id X. f \circ f^{-1} = id_Y \;\;\;\;\; and \;\;\;\;\; f^{-1} \circ f = id_X \,.

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

graphics grabbed from Munkres 75

(open interval homeomorphic to the real line)

The open interval (−1,1)(-1,1) is homeomorphic to all of the real line

(−1,1)≃homeoℝ 1. (-1,1) \underset{homeo}{\simeq} \mathbb{R}^1 \,.

An inverse pair of continuous functions is for instance given by

f : ℝ 1 ⟶ (−1,+1) x ↦ x1+x 2 \array{ f &\colon& \mathbb{R}^1 &\longrightarrow& (-1,+1) \\ && x &\mapsto& \frac{x}{\sqrt{1+ x^2}} }

and

f −1 : (−1,+1) ⟶ ℝ 1 x ↦ x1−x 2. \array{ f^{-1} &\colon& (-1,+1) &\longrightarrow& \mathbb{R}^1 \\ && x &\mapsto& \frac{x}{\sqrt{1 - x^2}} } \,.

Generally, every open ball in ℝ n\mathbb{R}^n (def. ) is homeomorphic to all of ℝ n\mathbb{R}^n.

(interval glued at endpoints is homeomorphic to the circle)

As topological spaces, the interval with its two endpoints identified is homeomorphic (def. ) to the standard circle:

[0,1] /(0∼1)≃homeoS 1. [0,1]_{/(0 \sim 1)} \;\; \underset{homeo}{\simeq} \;\; S^1 \,.

More in detail: let

S 1↪ℝ 2 S^1 \hookrightarrow \mathbb{R}^2

be the unit circle in the plane

S 1={(x,y)∈ℝ 2,x 2+y 2=1} S^1 = \{(x,y) \in \mathbb{R}^2, x^2 + y^2 = 1\}

equipped with the subspace topology (example ) of the plane ℝ 2\mathbb{R}^2, which itself equipped with its standard metric topology (example ).

Moreover, let

[0,1] /(0∼1) [0,1]_{/(0 \sim 1)}

be the quotient topological space (example ) obtained from the interval [0,1]⊂ℝ 1[0,1] \subset \mathbb{R}^1 with its subspace topology by applying the equivalence relation which identifies the two endpoints (and nothing else).

Consider then the function

f:[0,1]⟶S 1 f \;\colon\; [0,1] \longrightarrow S^1

given by

t↦(cos(2πt),sin(2πt)). t \mapsto (cos(2\pi t), sin(2\pi t)) \,.

This has the property that f(0)=f(1)f(0) = f(1), so that it descends to the quotient topological space

[0,1] ⟶ [0,1] /(0∼1) f↘ ↓ f˜ S 1. \array{ [0,1] &\overset{}{\longrightarrow}& [0,1]_{/(0 \sim 1)} \\ & {}_{\mathllap{f}}\searrow & \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\tilde f}} \\ && S^1 } \,.

We claim that f˜\tilde f is a homeomorphism (definition ).

First of all it is immediate that f˜\tilde f is a continuous function. This follows immediately from the fact that ff is a continuous function and by definition of the quotient topology (example ).

So we need to check that f˜\tilde f has a continuous inverse function. Clearly the restriction of ff itself to the open interval (0,1)(0,1) has a continuous inverse. It fails to have a continuous inverse on [0,1)[0,1) and on (0,1](0,1] and fails to have an inverse at all on [0,1], due to the fact that f(0)=f(1)f(0) = f(1). But the relation quotiented out in [0,1] /(0∼1)[0,1]_{/(0 \sim 1)} is exactly such as to fix this failure.

Similarly:

The square [0,1] 2[0,1]^2 with two of its sides identified is the cylinder, and with also the other two sides identified is the torus:

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

If the sides are identified with opposite orientation, the result is the Möbius strip:

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

graphics grabbed from Lawson 03

\,

Important examples of pairs of spaces that are not homeomorphic include the following:

The proof of theorem is surprisingly hard, given how obvious the statement seems intuitively. It requires tools from a field called algebraic topology (notably Brouwer's fixed point theorem).

We showcase some basic tools of algebraic topology now and demonstrate the nature of their usage by proving two very simple special cases of the topological invariance of dimension (prop. and prop. below).

\,

Homotopy

We have seen above that for n≥1n \geq 1 then the open ball B 0 ∘(1)B_0^\circ(1) in ℝ n\mathbb{R}^n is not homeomorphic to, notably, the point *=ℝ 0\ast = \mathbb{R}^0 (example , theorem ). Nevertheless, intuitively the nn-ball is a “continuous deformation” of the point, obtained as the radius of the nn-ball tends to zero.

This intuition is made precise by observing that there is a continuous function out of the product topological space (example ) of the open ball with the closed interval

η:[0,1]×B 0 ∘(1)⟶ℝ n \eta \colon [0,1] \times B_0^\circ(1) \longrightarrow \mathbb{R}^n

which is given by rescaling:

(t,x)↦t⋅x. (t,x) \mapsto t \cdot x \,.

This continuously interpolates between the open ball and the point in that for t=1t = 1 then it restricts to the defining inclusion B 0 ∘(1)B_0^\circ(1), while for t=0t = 0 then it restricts to the map constant on the origin.

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

We may summarize this situation by saying that there is a diagram of continuous functions of the form

B 0 ∘(1)×{0} ↓ ↘ x↦0 [0,1]×B 0 ∘(1) ⟶(t,x)↦t⋅x ℝ n ↑ ↗ inclusion B 0 ∘(1)×{1} \array{ B_0^\circ(1) \times \{0\} \\ \downarrow & \searrow^{\mathrlap{x \mapsto 0}} \\ [0,1] \times B_0^\circ(1) &\overset{(t,x) \mapsto t \cdot x}{\longrightarrow}& \mathbb{R}^n \\ \uparrow & \nearrow_{\mathrlap{inclusion}} \\ B_0^\circ(1) \times \{1\} }

Such “continuous deformations” are called homotopies:

(homotopy)

For f,g:X⟶Yf,g\colon X \longrightarrow Y two continuous functions between topological spaces X,YX,Y, then a (left) homotopy

η:f⇒ Lg \eta \colon f \,\Rightarrow_L\, g

is a continuous function

η:X×I⟶Y \eta \;\colon\; X \times I \longrightarrow Y

out of the product topological space (example ) of the open ball with the standard interval, such that this fits into a commuting diagram of the form

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

0×X (id,δ 0)↓ ↘ f [0,1]×X ⟶η Y (id,δ 1)↑ ↗ g {1}×X. \array{ {0} \times X \\ {}^{\mathllap{(id,\delta_0)}}\downarrow & \searrow^{\mathrlap{f}} \\ [0,1] \times X &\stackrel{\eta}{\longrightarrow}& Y \\ {}^{\mathllap{(id,\delta_1)}}\uparrow & \nearrow_{\mathrlap{g}} \\ \{1\} \times X } \,.

graphics grabbed from J. Tauber here

(homotopy equivalence)

A continuous function f:X⟶Yf \;\colon\; X \longrightarrow Y is called a homotopy equivalence if

  1. there exists a continuous function the other way around, g:Y⟶Xg \;\colon\; Y \longrightarrow X, and

  2. left homotopies, def. , from the two composites to the identity:

η 1:f∘g⇒ Lid Y \eta_1 \;\colon\; f\circ g \Rightarrow_L id_Y

and

η 2:g∘f⇒ Lid X. \eta_2 \;\colon\; g\circ f \Rightarrow_L id_X \,.

\,

Connected components

Using the concept of homotopy one obtains the basic tool of algebraic topology, namely the construction of algebraic homotopy invariants of topological spaces. We introduce the simplest and indicate their use.

A homotopy between two points

x,y:*→Xx,y \;\colon\; \ast \to X

is a continuous path between these points.

This construction is evidently compatible with composition, in that

π 0(g∘f)=π 0(g)∘π 0(f) \pi_0(g \circ f) = \pi_0(g) \circ \pi_0(f)

and it evidently is unital, in that

π 0(id X)=id π 0(X). \pi_0(id_X) = id_{\pi_{0}(X)} \,.

One summarizes this by saying that π 0\pi_0 is a functor from the category Top of topological spaces to the category Set of sets, denoted

π 0:Top⟶Set. \pi_0 \;\colon\; Top \longrightarrow Set \,.

An immediate but important consequence is this:

Since π 0\pi_0 is functorial, it immediately follows that it sends isomorphisms to isomorphisms, hence homeomorphisms to bijections:

f∘g=idandg∘f=id ⇒ π 0(f∘g)=π 0(id)andπ 0(g∘f)=π 0(id) ⇔ π 0(f)∘π 0(g)=idandπ 0(g)∘π 0(f)=id. \begin{aligned} & f \circ g = id \;\;and\;\; g \circ f = id \\ \Rightarrow \;\;\;\;\;\;& \pi_0(f \circ g) = \pi_0(id) \;\;and \;\; \pi_0(g \circ f) = \pi_0(id) \\ \Leftrightarrow \;\;\;\;\;\; & \pi_0(f) \circ \pi_0(g) = id \;\;and \;\; \pi_0(g) \circ \pi_0(f) = id \end{aligned} \,.

This means that we may use path connected components as a first “topological invariant” that allows us to distinguish some topological spaces.

As an example for how this is being used, we have the following proof of a simple special case of the topological invariance of dimension (theorem ):

Assume there were a homeomorphism

f:ℝ 1⟶ℝ 2 f \colon \mathbb{R}^1 \longrightarrow \mathbb{R}^2

we will derive a contradiction. If ff is a homeomorphism, then clearly so is its restriction to the topological subspaces (example ) obtained by removing 0∈ℝ 10 \in \mathbb{R}^1 and f(0)∈ℝ 2f(0) \in \mathbb{R}^2.

f:(ℝ 1−{0})⟶(ℝ 2−{f(0)}). f \;\colon\; (\mathbb{R}^1-\{0\}) \longrightarrow (\mathbb{R}^2 - \{f(0)\}) \,.

It follows that we would get a bijection of connected components between π 0(ℝ 1−{0})\pi_0(\mathbb{R}^1 - \{0\}) and π 0(ℝ 2−{f(0)})\pi_0(\mathbb{R}^2 - \{f(0)\}). But clearly the first set has two elements, while the second has just one:

π 0(ℝ 1−{0})≠π 0(ℝ 2−{f(0)}). \pi_0(\mathbb{R}^1-\{0\}) \;\neq\; \pi_0(\mathbb{R}^2 - \{f(0)\}) \,.

The key lesson of the proof of prop. is its strategy:

Of course in practice one uses more sophisticated invariants than just π 0\pi_0.

The next topological invariant after the connected components is the fundamental group:

Fundamental group

(fundamental group)

Let XX be a topological space and let x∈Xx \in X be a chosen point. Then write

π 1(X,x)∈Grp \pi_1(X,x) \;\in\; Grp

for, to start with, the set of homotopy classes of paths in XX that start and end at xx. Such paths are also called the continuous loops in XX based at xx.

  1. Under concatenation of loops, π 1(X,x)\pi_1(X,x) becomes a semi-group.

  2. The constant loop is a neutral element under this composition (thus making π 1(X,x)\pi_1(X,x) a “monoid”).

  3. The reverse of a loop is its inverse in π 1(X,x)\pi_1(X,x), making π 1(X,x)\pi_1(X,x) indeed into a group.

This is called the fundamental group of XX at xx.

The following picture indicates the four non-equivalent non-trivial generators of the fundamental group of the oriented surface of genus 2:

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

graphics grabbed from Lawson 03

Again, this operation is functorial, now on the category Top */Top^{\ast/} of pointed topological spaces, whose objects are topological spaces equipped with a chosen point, and whose morphisms are continuous maps f:X→Yf \colon X \to Y that take the chosen basepoint of XX to that of YY:

π 1:Top */⟶Grp. \pi_1 \;\colon\; Top^{\ast/} \longrightarrow Grp \,.

As π 0\pi_0, so also π 1\pi_1 is a topological invariant. As before, we may use this to prove a simple case of the theorem of the topological invariance of dimension:

Assume there were such a homeomorphism ff; we will derive a contradiction.

If ff is a homeomorphism, then so is its restriction to removing the origin from ℝ 2\mathbb{R}^2 and f(0)f(0) from ℝ 3\mathbb{R}^3:

(ℝ 2−{0})⟶(ℝ 3−{f(0)}). (\mathbb{R}^2 - \{0\}) \longrightarrow (\mathbb{R}^3 - \{f(0)\}) \,.

Thse two spaces are both path-connected, hence π 0\pi_0 does not distiguish them.

But they do have different fundamental groups π 1\pi_1:

  1. The fundamental group of ℝ 2−{0}\mathbb{R}^{2} - \{0\} is ℤ\mathbb{Z} (counting the winding of loops around the removed point). We discuss this further below in example .

  2. The fundamental group of ℝ 3−{f(0)}\mathbb{R}^3 - \{f(0)\} is trivial: because the single removed point is no obstruction to sliding loops past it and contracting them.

But since passing to fundamental groups is functorial, the same argument as in the proof of prop. shows that ff cannot be an isomorphism, hence not a homeomorphism.

We now discuss a “dual incarnation” of fundamental groups, which often helps to compute them.

Covering spaces

(covering space)

A covering space of a topological space XX is a continuous map

p:E→X p \colon E \to X

such that there exists an open cover ⊔iU i→X\underset{i}{\sqcup}U_i \to X, such that restricted to each U iU_i then E→XE \to X is homeomorphic over U iU_i to the product topological space (example ) of U iU_i with the discrete topological space (example ) on a set F iF_i

⊔iU i×F i ⟶ E ↓ (pb) ↓ p ⊔iU i ⟶ X. \array{ \underset{i}{\sqcup} U_i \times F_i &\longrightarrow& E \\ \downarrow &(pb)& \downarrow^{\mathrlap{p}} \\ \underset{i}{\sqcup} U_i &\underset{}{\longrightarrow}& X } \,.

For x∈U i⊂Xx \in U_i \subset X a point, then the elements in F x=F iF_x = F_i are called the leaves of the covering at xx.

(covering of circle by circle)

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

Regard the circle S 1={z∈ℂ||z|=1}S^1 = \{ z \in \mathbb{C} \;\vert\; {\vert z\vert} = 1 \} as the topological subspace of elements of unit absolute value in the complex plane. For k∈ℕk \in \mathbb{N}, consider the continuous function

p≔(−) k:S 1⟶S 1 p \coloneqq (-)^k \;\colon\; S^1 \longrightarrow S^1

given by taking a complex number to its kkth power. This may be thought of as the result of “winding the circle kk times around itself”. Precisely, for k≥1k \geq 1 this is a covering space (def. ) with kk leaves at each point.

graphics grabbed from Hatcher

(covering of circle by real line)

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

Consider the continuous function

exp(2πi(−)):ℝ 1⟶S 1 \exp(2 \pi i(-)) \;\colon\; \mathbb{R}^1 \longrightarrow S^1

from the real line to the circle, which,

  1. with the circle regarded as the unit circle in the complex plane ℂ\mathbb{C}, is given by

    t↦exp(2πit) t \mapsto \exp(2\pi i t)

  2. with the circle regarded as the unit circle in ℝ 2\mathbb{R}^2, is given by

    t↦(cos(2πt),sin(2πt)). t \mapsto ( cos(2\pi t), sin(2\pi t) ) \,.

We may think of this as the result of “winding the line around the circle ad infinitum”. Precisely, this is a covering space (def. ) with the leaves at each point forming the set ℤ\mathbb{Z} of natural numbers.

(action of fundamental group on fibers of covering)

Let E⟶πXE \overset{\pi}{\longrightarrow} X be a covering space (def. )

Then for x∈Xx \in X any point, and any choice of element e∈F xe \in F_x of the leaf space over xx, there is, up to homotopy, a unique way to lift a representative path in XX of an element γ\gamma of the the fundamental group π 1(X,x)\pi_1(X,x) (def. ) to a continuous path in EE that starts at ee. This path necessarily ends at some (other) point ρ γ(e)∈F x\rho_\gamma(e) \in F_x in the same fiber. This construction provides a function

ρ : F x×π 1(X,x) ⟶ F x (e,γ) ↦ ρ γ(e) \array{ \rho &\colon& F_x \times \pi_1(X,x) &\longrightarrow& F_x \\ && (e,\gamma) &\mapsto& \rho_\gamma(e) }

from the Cartesian product of the leaf space with the fundamental group. This function is compatible with the group-structure on π 1(X,x)\pi_1(X,x), in that the following diagrams commute:

F x×{const x} ⟶ F x×π 1(X,x) id↘ ↙ ρ F x(the neutral element, i.e. the constant loop, acts trivially) \array{ F_x \times \{const_x\} && \longrightarrow && F_x \times \pi_1(X,x) \\ & {}_{\mathllap{id}}\searrow && \swarrow_{\mathrlap{\rho}} \\ && F_x } \;\;\;\;\;\; \left( \array{ \text{the neutral element,} \\ \text{i.e. the constant loop,} \\ \text{acts trivially} } \right)

and

F x×π 1(X,x)×π 1(X,x) ⟶ρ×id F x×π 1(X,x) id×((−)⋅(−))↓ ↓ ρ F x×π 1(X,x) ⟶ρ F x(acting with two group elements is the same as first multiplying them and then acting with their product element). \array{ F_x \times \pi_1(X,x) \times \pi_1(X,x) &\overset{\rho \times id}{\longrightarrow}& F_x \times \pi_1(X,x) \\ {}^{\mathllap{id \times ((-)\cdot(-))}}\downarrow && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\rho}} \\ F_x \times \pi_1(X,x) &\underset{\rho}{\longrightarrow}& F_x } \;\;\;\;\;\; \left( \array{ \text{acting with two group elements } \\ \text{is the same as} \\ \text{first multiplying them} \\ \text{ and then acting with their product element} } \right) \,.

One says that ρ\rho is an action or permutation representation of π 1(X,x)\pi_1(X,x) on F xF_x.

For GG any group, then there is a category GSetG Set whose objects are sets equipped with an action of GG, and whose morphisms are functions which respect these actions. The above construction yields a functor

Cov(X)⟶π 1(X,x)Set. Cov(X) \longrightarrow \pi_1(X,x) Set \,.

(three-sheeted covers of the circle)

Algebraic topology vs point-set topology

There are, up to isomorphism, three different 3-sheeted covering spaces of the circle S 1S^1.

The one from example for k=3k = 3. Another one. And the trivial one. Their corresponding permutation actions may be seen from the pictures on the right.

graphics grabbed from Hatcher

We are now ready to state the main theorem about the fundamental group. Except that it does require the following slightly technical condition on the base topological space. This condition is satisfied for all “reasonable” topological spaces:

(fundamental theorem of covering spaces)

Let XX be a topological space which is path-connected (def. ), locally path connected (def. ) and semi-locally simply connected (def. ). Then for any x∈Xx \in X the functor

Fib x:Cov(X)⟶π 1(X,x)Set. Fib_x \;\colon\; Cov(X) \overset{}{\longrightarrow} \pi_1(X,x) Set \,.

from def. that describes the action of the fundamental group of XX on the set of leaves over xx has the following property:

A functor with these two properties one calls an equivalence of categories:

Cov(X)⟶≃π 1(X,x)Set. Cov(X) \overset{\simeq}{\longrightarrow} \pi_1(X,x) Set \,.

This has some interesting implications:

Every sufficiently nice topological space XX as above has a covering which is simply connected (def. ). This is the covering corresponding, under the fundamental theorem of covering spaces (theorem ) to the action of π 1(X)\pi_1(X) on itself. This is called the universal covering space X^→X\hat X \to X. The above theorem implies that the fundamental group itself may be recovered as the automorphisms of the universal covering space:

π 1(X)≃Aut Cov /X(X^,X^). \pi_1(X) \simeq Aut_{Cov_{/X}}(\hat X, \hat X) \,.

(computing the fundamental group of the circle)

The covering exp(2πi(−)):ℝ 1→S 1\exp(2\pi i(-)) \;\colon\; \mathbb{R}^1 \to S^1 from example is simply connected (def. ), hence must be the universal covering space, up to homeomorphism.

It is fairly straightforward to see that the only homeomorphisms from ℝ 1\mathbb{R}^1 to itself over S 1S^1 are given by integer translations by n∈ℕ↪ℝn \in \mathbb{N} \hookrightarrow \mathbb{R}:

ℝ 1 ⟶≃t↦t+n ℝ 1 exp(2πi(−))↘ ↙ exp(2πi(−)) S 1. \array{ \mathbb{R}^1 && \underoverset{\simeq}{t \mapsto t + n}{\longrightarrow} && \mathbb{R}^1 \\ & {}_{\mathllap{\exp(2 \pi i(-))}}\searrow && \swarrow_{\mathrlap{\exp(2 \pi i(-))}} \\ && S^1 } \,.

Hence

Aut Cov /S 1(S^ 1,S^ 1)≃ℤ Aut_{Cov_{/S^1}}(\hat S^1, \hat S^1) \simeq \mathbb{Z}

and hence the fundamental group of the circle is the additive group of integers:

π 1(S 1)≃ℤ. \pi_1(S^1) \simeq \mathbb{Z} \,.

\,

\,

Basic facts

Central theorems

The following is an (incomplete) list of available nnLab entries related to topology.

Topological spaces

  • TopCW-complex, general topology

  • induced topology, subspace, interior, boundary, closure

  • product topological space, disjoint union topological space

  • sphere, metric space, metrizable space

  • topological space, continuous map, homeomorphism, neighborhood

  • pointed space, contractible space, connected space, second countable space

  • convergence space, pretopological space, pseudotopological space, coarse topology

  • metric space, filtered space, connected filtered space, complete space, net, Polish space

  • separation axioms, Hausdorff space, regular space, normal space

  • noetherian topological space, irreducible topological space

  • compact space, locally compact space, compactum, paracompact space

  • Frechet-Uryson space, sequential space, uniform space

  • convenient category of topological spaces, compactly generated space

  • nice topological space, nice category of spaces

  • pointless topology, locale, cover, site, ringed space

sphere

  • Sierpinski space, Warsaw circle

See also examples in topology.

Manifolds and generalizations

Algebraic topology and homotopy theory

  • homotopy, homotopy inverse, homotopy theory, homotopy equivalence, rational homotopy theory

  • shape theory, algebraic topology

  • model category, category of fibrant objects, Quillen adjunction, Quillen equivalence, category with weak equivalences,

  • model 2-category, model stack

  • Reedy category, Reedy model structure, generalized Reedy category

  • model structure on chain complexes, model structure on crossed complexes

  • homotopy hypothesis, homotopy theory of Grothendieck, test category

  • homotopy limit, homotopy colimit, homotopy pullback, homotopy image, homotopy coherent category theory, homotopy coherent nerve, Brown representability theorem

  • homotopy type, homotopy 1-type, homotopy 2-type, homotopy 3-type, homotopy n-type

  • deformation retract, neighborhood retract, Postnikov system

  • fundamental group, homotopy group, suspension, Freudenthal suspension theorem, delooping

  • loop space, free loop space object,

  • cup product, Dold-Thom theorem

Topological homotopy theory

  • classical model structure on topological spaces

  • topological group, H-space, co-H-space

  • principal bundle, fiber bundle, vector bundle, principal 2-bundle, trivial bundle

  • fibration, Hurewicz fibration, Hurewicz connection, homotopy lifting property, Dold fibration

  • homotopy extension property, Hurewicz cofibration, deformation retract, model structure on topological spaces, Strøm's theorem

  • cocylinder, cylinder object, path object, mapping cone, path groupoid, path n-groupoid, fundamental groupoid

  • classifying space, Eilenberg-MacLane space,Moore space, Moore path category

  • spectrum, smash product of spectra, symmetric spectrum, stable (infinity,1)-category, commutative ring spectrum

Simplicial homotopy theory

  • classical model structure on simplicial sets

  • simplicial set, simplex category, simplicial identities, simplicial object, cosimplicial object

  • simplicial complex, singular simplicial complex,

  • boundary of a simplex, simplicial skeleton, category of simplices

  • combinatorial spectrum, simplicial groupoid, simplicial model category

  • simplicially enriched category, quasicategory, Segal category, complete Segal space

  • Kan fibration, Kan complex, nerve, nerve and realization, simplicial homotopy, simplicial homotopy group, simplicial local system

  • simplicial presheaf, local model structure on simplicial presheaves, local model structure on simplicial sheaves

  • marked simplicial set, model structure on marked simplicial over-sets, infinity topos, Higher Topos Theory

  • dendroidal set, model structure on dendroidal sets, cubical set, cellular set, cyclic object, Theta space

Sheaves, stacks, cohomology

  • site, sheaf, flabby sheaf, local epimorphism, etale space, hypercover
  • topos
  • cohomology, sheaf cohomology, abelian sheaf cohomology, local system, category of sheaves
  • Čech cohomology, Bredon cohomology, twisted cohomology, twisting cochain
  • nonabelian algebraic topology, nonabelian cocycle, nonabelian cohomology
  • principal infinity-bundle, BrownAHT, category of fibrant objects
  • topological K-theory, gerbe, twisted K-theory, Karoubi K-theory, differential K-theory, K-theory spectrum
  • de Rham cohomology, string topology
  • Thom space, Thom bundle?, fiber integration, equivariant cohomology
  • Poincaré duality, Spanier-Whitehead duality
  • generalized cohomology, generalized (Eilenberg-Steenrod) cohomology, generalized (Eilenberg-Steenrod) homotopy
  • topological stack, orbispace
  • topological quantum field theory, tmf, cobordism hypothesis, topological T-duality
  • characteristic class, Chern-Weil theory

Non-commutative topology

  • noncommutative topology

    • C-star-algebra, KK-theory

Computational Topology

References

Historical origins:

Textbook accounts:

  • John Kelley, General topology, D. van Nostrand, New York 1955, reprinted as: Graduate Texts in Mathematics, Springer 1955 (ISBN:978-0-387-90125-1)

  • James Dugundji, Topology, Allyn and Bacon 1966 (pdf)

  • Nicolas Bourbaki, Chapter 1 of: Topological Structures of Elements of Mathematics III: General topology, Springer 1971, 1990

  • James Munkres, Topology, Prentice Hall 1975 (2000)

  • Ryszard Engelking, General Topology, Sigma series in pure mathematics 6, Heldermann 1989 (ISBN 388538-006-4)

  • Steven Vickers, Topology via Logic, Cambridge University Press (1989) (toc pdf)

  • Glen Bredon, Topology and Geometry, Graduate texts in mathematics 139, Springer 1993 (doi:10.1007/978-1-4757-6848-0, pdf)

  • Terry Lawson, Topology: A Geometric Approach, Oxford University Press (2003) (pdf)

See also:

With emphasis on category theoretic aspects of general topology:

  • Horst Herrlich, George Strecker, Categorical topology – Its origins as exemplified by the unfolding of the theory of topological reflections and coreflections before 1971 (pdf), pages 255-341 in: C. E. Aull, R Lowen (eds.), Handbook of the History of General Topology. Vol. 1, Kluwer 1997 (doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0468-7)

  • Tai-Danae Bradley, Tyler Bryson, John Terilla, Topology – A categorical approach, MIT Press 2020 (ISBN:9780262539357, web version)

See also

  • Alan Hatcher, Algebraic Topology

and see further references at algebraic topology.

Lecture notes:

Basic topology set up in intuitionistic mathematics is discussed in

  • Franka Waaldijk, modern intuitionistic topology, 1996 (pdf)

See also:

  • Topospaces, a Wiki with basic material on topology.